Are Mountains Real?

[Post at Preface to Atheism, Apr 27, 2024.]

When philosophers ask if something is real, they mean: Does it exist independently of our thoughts?

Whose thoughts, exactly? Well, generally, human thoughts. Our in this context means us as a species.

But what if we aren’t the only creatures who have thoughts? What if cetaceans have thoughts—or great apes—or birds—or aliens living in a galaxy far, far away?

In my last post, we saw that Elon Musk believes that our earth exists independently of our (human) thoughts but almost certainly not (“only one chance in billions”) independently of the thoughts/experiences of some unspecified aliens (presumably with their supercomputers) somewhere far, far away.

For that matter (according to most who hold a supernatural worldview) there is a Godout there who also thinks—and who originally thought us and our world into existence.

Idealism

So when we ask whether or not something is real, we have two questions: “Does it exist independently of our thoughts?” and the broader question, “Does it exist independently of all thought, including thoughts of powerful aliens and God?”

The answers might not be the same.

Consider George Berkeley’s idealism.

Is the physical world around us real? Does it exist independently of our thoughts? Berkeley would say yes. But does it exist independently of God’s thoughts? He would say no.

His idealism has to be taken seriously because Berkeley presented a strong case for the conclusion that objects are mental in nature—that objects are not independent of thought.

We’ll get to this in a moment, when we ask if mountains are real (that is, independent of thought). But first I want to point out that idealism is not the standard viewpoint for most people who believe in God.

The standard (Christian & Muslim) viewpoint is this: Yes, the physical world was created by God (e.g. God thought it into existence) but once created, the world exists independently of what anyone thinks about it (whether the thinker is human or alien or even God).

Philosophers call this external world realism (or thought-independent realism or observer-independent realism—you get the idea).

If I see a mountain and start climbing it, there really is a mountain independent of my own mind (and body) which I am climbing. Independent of God’s mind too. As we say, the mountain is real.

Or is it?

You are probably thinking, how can Berkeley (or anyone whose feet are solidly on the ground) sincerely doubt the mind-independent existence of the mountain.

Answer: by thinking carefully about what a mountain is. And, as we will see, what a valley is.

If you read one of my earlier posts, Roundness and what is real, you may have an idea of where we are going.

A mountain is an object. A physical object, right? But what defines the object?

Is it a giant agglomeration of rock and dirt which rises above the valley? Does mountain include trees and bushes growing on it? The birds flying around and landing on branches? As we trudge up the mountain path and raise dust, is the dust raised part of the mountain? Or is it not? Will it become part of the mountain again if it settles back on the ground? How close to settling on the ground (or leaves) must it be?

For that matter, where does the base of the mountain end? Does it end at the bank of the river in the valley below, at the point where the flowing water ceases to make the ground wet? Does the answer depend on how much rain there was last night?

But wait—the bank of the river and its surrounding flood plain is part of the valley, not the mountain, right? Can a spot of land belong both to the mountain and the valley at once?

So where exactly does mountain meet valley? And when I say exactly, I mean exactly: show me the dividing line down to the square millimeter (or molecule or electron or smaller) where one side is mountain and the other side is valley.

Well you can’t. Or if you can it is utterly arbitrary. In fact, the divide is whatever anyone chooses it to be.

This is a problem for the claim that the mountain (or the valley) is independent of thought.

Notice that we can’t avoid the difficulty here by trying to distinguish between mountain as a category (clearly a mental construction) and an individual instance of a mountain (hopefully not a mental construction). We like to give individual mountains names, but does this make them less of a mental construction?

Consider: Cowrock Mountain and Wildcat Mountain in north Georgia overlook a beautiful valley formed by Town Creek. Yet given this specific instance we still have the difficulty of precisely identifying the mountains’ boundaries with the valley. So we see that individual instances require us to either be vague or to adopt utterly ad-hoc boundaries.

Such decisions are necessarily arbitrary, and therefore necessarily mental in nature.

A mountain is a mental object.

Or as soon as we try to define the mountain, it becomes a mental object.

Objects and meanings

In short, a mountain is a meaning. Even specific mountains like Cowrock and Wildcat are meanings.

Indeed, all objects are meanings, with their assigned properties and qualities. And so, as soon as we think about something, about mountains and valleys for instance, they can’t be thought-independent.

This sounds like a truism. But in reality, it’s just an obvious fact of our existence. The moment we try to know the world, we are inextricably dealing with the world of thoughts. Everything in that world is mental. None of the objects and properties and relationships and boundaries that we could ever think about will be or could be thought-independent.

Still, aren’t we thinking about something out there? Something which really isindependent of our thoughts?

Yes.

Only, nothing we think about stuff “out there” can ever be thought-independent. Meanings can never be thought-independent: they are the very stuff of thinking.

Any object we imagine can never be “out there” because by their very nature objects are meaningful things formed and existingin here”, in our thoughts.

Still, we want to say that when we look at the mountain (or are climbing it) there is a real, thought-independent thing there in front of us. We can interact with it. We dointeract with it.

But our thoughts do not.

Our thoughts are only “about” it. Thoughts, in other words, are of a fundamentally different nature than physical reality.

What would Berkeley say?

Berkeley would disagree. He argued that the mental object, with its meanings and properties et al, is precisely what exists out there.

This “physical” world consisting of numerous objects with properties is—Berkeley acknowledged—independent of our human minds. You know this if you’ve ever lost a sock doing laundry, and then months or years later, discovered the sock behind the dryer. The sock clearly had its own existence, separate from your thoughts, all along.

Objects (and their associated properties) out there in the world persist even when wedon’t think about them (or forget they exist). Berkeley wondered how this could be so, if objects are mental stuff—that is, mind-dependent.

And his answer was: God.

God keeps all objects in mind all the time, thus insuring their enduring existence even when our own minds forget about them.

External world realism and object anti-realism

But Berkeley’s solution to the discovery that objects are mental constructions—it’s not the only possibility.

The other possibility is that there is stuff out there in the external world of a fundamentally different nature than the nature of mental objects constructed by minds.

The objects we experience—yes, they are mental constructions—but as such “stand in” for non-mental stuff out there in the external world. That external stuff maintains its existence not because it’s a bunch of mental objects constructed in God’s mind, but rather because it’s non-mental in its very nature.

Under this view, there is no direct connection or correspondence between external world stuff and our mental constructions. The meaningful objects we imagine are substitutes, mappings at best. The mountain object in our mind stands in for the (very real) external reality that we are climbing. It persists, even when we are not climbing it—not because God’s mind has the mountain object in divine view—but because the thing we are climbing is not an object at all, not a mental construct in any sense.

I hope the reader understands that I’m trying to draw an impenetrable divide between objects—which are mental constructs (Berkeley was right on this point)—and real(mind-independent) “physical” stuff.1

Two important points flow from this. The first is that although we are asserting realism(thought-independence) regarding the external world, we are asserting anti-realismregarding objects (including scientific objects), properties, and relationships between objects and properties. This is also anti-realism regarding mathematics, quantities, universals of any sort, and so on. All are mental elements and therefore exist only in our thoughts.2

This is also anti-realism about what we see, hear, touch, smell and taste. We think our senses are sensations coming to us from the world out there. They are not. Our brain constructs them so that we have subjective experiences which appear to us to be the world but in fact are a simulation—a sensory stand-in for the world. The stand-in only exists inside us.

Anti-realism, as far as the mountain goes, means the mountain (as soon as we sense it or conceive of it as a mountain) is a mental construction, and therefore thought-dependent rather than independent.3 The assertion that objects are not thought-independent is called object anti-realism.

Again, this includes scientific objects. Why? Because scientists can’t think about their subject without conceiving of objects, and these objects are necessarily mental constructions—even though they are meant to stand in for real stuff in the external world.

The second point, which helps explain the first, is an assertion about what thoughts and meanings and objects and properties are: sensations produced by the brain.

Thought can’t escape being a sensation—that is, an experience we have. Objects, even scientific objects, are necessarily experiences occurring within the brain and created by its neurons.

In short, meanings are a type of sensation produced by our neurons.4

Furthermore, sensations (including meaning sensations) interact only with the neurons in our brain. There is no interaction outside of this sphere. Our consciousness, our thoughts, our mind, is only a production by the brain done for its benefit.5

This means that there is no interaction between our sensations and the world “out there.”

We don’t perceive the world, in other words.

We don’t see it. We don’t hear it. We don’t smell it. We don’t taste it. We don’t even feelit.

Our bodies interact with the world, certainly. From these interactions, our brains create sensations—including the five senses and sensations of meaning—which our brains then use as a stand in for the outside world. (Think of the stand-in as the visual, auditory, tactile, aromatic experiences you have, combined with “objectification” which create objects with properties and joined with “meanings” tacked on by (probably) the neocortex.

The stand-in is composed not just of our sensory experiences but also has these tacked on meanings about objects within the stand-in.

All this happens and exists within the brain, and does not constitute an interaction with the world out there. Our bodies (not our sensations) interact with the out thereand send signals to the brain, which then produces the stand in (again, our sensations and thoughts) for the “out there”—which we then use as a guide for our actions.6

So is the stand in an accurate representation of out there?

It can’t be. There is no direct interaction between the stand in and the surrounding world.

However, what we can say is that the stand in is a useful representation of whatever is out there. If it’s not useful enough, we don’t survive.

So the brain is constantly trying to improve the stand in based on our interactions with the world. Much of the improvement goes beyond the initial sensations of our senses and involves changing our meanings, our mental stuff.

All this is to try to make the stand in as useful to us as possible.

Summary

So if we pull everything I’ve written together, what we get is this:

The nature of the “physical” world and the nature of thoughts (consciousness) are completely unlike each other. Philosophers call this dualism.

The alternative is to say they are the same, adopt Berkeley’s idealism and bring in God to explain why the external world has independence from our thoughts (though not from God’s).

But dualism wasn’t the original state of things.

Originally—per naturalism—consciousness did not exist. It arrived on the scene after billions of years of evolution, when it finally began to be produced by neurons in the brains of some species of animals on earth.

So dualism only emerged with the development of brains capable of producing subjective sensations.

Because of this evolutionary development, no sensations, thoughts or meanings can match the actual nature of the world around us (evolution has no way to pull that off)—indeed they can only be a stand-in, a simulacrum, a representation created in a different medium.

We can’t know the mind-independent external world as it is.

Surprisingly, this doesn’t matter to us because we modify the stand in using pragmatic empiricism—that is, our brain creates a sensual stand-in with hooks for meanings which we then constantly try to improve to be as useful a stand-in for the world as possible.

How do we do this? By acting in the world and noticing what works better and adjusting our understanding accordingly.

Hopefully this makes sense. And if it does, then hopefully you’ll understand why I describe this as philosophical naturalism based on philosophical skepticism.

And in fact, maybe you can see why I say this is actually a scientific meta-hypothesis (an hypothesis which ties in and gives context to a large range of other scientific hypotheses).7

Footnotes

1

I put “physical” in quotes here for a reason. Whatever the stuff of the mind-independent reality is composed of, it is not mental in nature. It’s not objects with properties and relationships—those are necessarily mental constructs. “Physical” means meaning-independent, and that is all. (Meaning-independent entails mind-independence and thought-independence.) Thus we employ the term “physical” for primarily for historical reasons: it’s the traditional term for the stuff physicists and physical scientists try to study. But whatever it is, it not made up of objects or properties, which are unavoidably mental in nature. Knowledge is a stand-in for the thought-independent whatever-it-is around us. Which highlights the importance of distinguishing the whatever-it-is from our thoughts about it.

2

Admittedly, my object anti-realism becomes softer when we consider organisms.

3

Technically the brain is constructing three distinguishable things here. First, it’s constructing a sensual visual/auditory/felt simulacra which stand in for the world; second, it’s integrating the various simulacra (via synesthesia) and populating them with objects and associated properties; third it’s integrating understandings and knowledge about those objects and properties into the stand-in. Then, as an organism, we act within the world and adjust the stand-in appropriately to make it as useful to us as possible.

4

Even what we call information is really composed of sensations we experience inside us—properly speaking information is not out there. More on this in a future post.

5

As I like to say, mind (consciousness) is a major way the brain goes about improving itself so it can make better decisions in the future. Consciousness serves the brain and the brain serves the body.

6

I plan a future post that will dive into this using vision as an example. If the reader is interested, I recommend Donald Hoffman’s book, Visual Intelligence: How We Create What We See.

7

Notice that I am not asserting that science is committed to methodological naturalism—not at all. Instead, scientists are free to entertain alternatives to naturalism. Scientists could—if it worked well—adopt one or another meta-hypothesis of supernaturalism. Nothing prevents this. What I maintain is that naturalism as a meta-hypothesis simply works better, and will be found to be more useful.

Posted in Naturalism, Nature of Knowledge, Simulacrum | Leave a comment

Elon Musk is bad at math

[Post at Preface to Atheism, Apr 11, 2024]

Is Elon Musk bad at mathematics? The suggestion may not shock readers who remember him foolishly paying $44 billion for Twitter (now X).

For that I give him a pass. He wanted Twitter badly and to him cost was almost an after-thought.1

Instead I want to focus on an egregious example of Elon’s math illiteracy.

He has famously claimed that we almost certainly live inside a simulation (there’s only a one in billion chance that we don’t, he said). To my knowledge, Elon still maintains this.2

At Code Conference 2016, Elon presented the math this way:

The strongest argument for us being in a simulation—probably being in a simulation—I think, is the following. Forty years ago we had Pong—like, two rectangles and a dot. That is what games were. Now forty years later we have photo-realistic 3-D simulations with millions of people playing simultaneously, and it’s getting better every year. And people have virtual reality, augmented reality. If you assume any rate of improvement at all, then the games will become indistinguishable from reality. Indistinguishable. Even if the rate of advancement drops by a thousand from what it is right now, then you just say, okay, let’s imagine 10,000 years in the future, which is nothing in the evolutionary scale. Given that we’re clearly on a trajectory to have games that are indistinguishable from reality, and those games could be played on any set-top box or on a PC or whatever, and there would probably be billions of such computers and set-top boxes, it would seem to follow that the odds that we’re in base reality is one in billions. Tell me what’s wrong with that argument? … Is there a flaw in that argument? … There’s a one in billion chance that this is base reality. … I think it’s one in billions.3

Well, actually, Elon, there’s a massive mathematical flaw in your argument.

No one spoke up because, well, you’re the richest (second richest?) man in the world. Yet you’re the Emperor with no clothes.

Red Herrings

The problem is this: Elon thinks the number of human-built computers running human-created virtual reality games “indistinguishable from reality” is pertinent to calculating the odds that we humans ourselves exist in a similar virtual reality.

That’s a math blunder.

He’s spewing numbers which have nothing to do with the proposition at hand.

If you took high school math, you likely encountered “word problems” with specious information—numbers thrown in which are immaterial to calculating the answer. That’s what Elon does here—obviously without realizing it.

Why is the number of virtual reality games indistinguishable from reality, whether running on set-top boxes, laptops, VR headsets, VR glasses, even AR/VR contact lens in the future—why is it immaterial?

Because the one sure thing we know about all these games—now or in the future—is that human beings created them, human beings are playing them, and although the games create an illusion of us being immersed within the game’s world and interacting with its characters, we nevertheless still exist outside it all.

Necessarily so, since we humans will have built (or at least purchased) the hardware and downloaded the AR or VR program running on it. Some of us will work in the data centers which host the servers necessary for simultaneous play, and so on.

After all, Elon’s claim is not that we will someday magically find ourselves trappedinside our own games because they have reached some critical level of realism—at least I hope no one reading this is so dissociated from reality.

Elon’s claim is that some superior, alien intelligence, unknown to us, has created this reality that we live in, just as we (now or in the future) create virtual realities which seem just like the world around us—and that the fictional characters we create in these future games will have consciousness and be alive just as we are.

And yet—whatever worlds we create will nevertheless exist within our world and its realities. For example, a power outage or battery failure will still bring the game to a crashing end. But the power outage will not end us.

Likewise, food we consume within the virtual reality will not actually end up in our stomachs, unless we concurrently eat in real life. If this is not clear, please see a medical professional (preferably IRL).

So the billion virtual reality games 10,000 years from now are a red herring. Not a single one of them will be an example of a virtual world within which we biologicallyexist or in which any fictional character in any fictional game biologically exists.

Thus it’s mathematically invalid to use them to estimate odds that our own biologically existence occurs inside a simulation.

To Be Clear…

If this is not clear, let me help you understand it mathematically, step by step.

Take an actual, biologically produced orange (one plucked from a tree or purchased from a grocery store) and put it on a table in front of you. What do you have?

A table with an orange (which you could peel and eat if desired) on it. How likely is it that the orange is not real but a simulation?

If you are unsure, peel it and eat it—was it a simulation or did something actually go into your stomach?

Okay, if you ate the orange, pluck or buy another and put it on the table.

Now let’s add the red herring. Or rather red apples. A billion red apples. More specifically, a billion simulated red apples. (You can use your Google Glasses or Meta Quest or Vision Pro to simulate the apples. And yes, you’ll need to make the table bigger.)

Math quiz: did adding the billion apples make it more likely that the original orange on the table is now not an orange at all but an apple?

Did the orange transform into something it is not because we imagined (or simulated) a billion apples?

No.

Does creating a simulated apple mean that all apples and all oranges and all tables and all people must be simulated?

No.

But what if we create a billion, tens of billions, hundreds of trillions of simulated apples?

No. The orange is still an orange.

All Elon has done is: introduce a billion red herrings and gob-smack himself with the large number of simulated herrings floating around in his head.

In Elon’s Defense

Wait.

Maybe Elon thinks the orange was an apple all along. Maybe he thinks all fruit, by definition, are simulated fruit. Oranges don’t exist unless simulated.

There is almost some truth to this.

When I see an orange on the table, my brain creates my experience—the roundness, the color, the citric smell and so on. These orange properties are produced by my brain to create a virtual reality “orange” which stands in for the physical whatever lying on the table.

Not only that, in similar fashion my brain created the table, the room, everything.

The simulation is inside me.

It’s my creation.

So wait—is there anything outside me, outside the virtual reality created by my brain? Is there a physical orange, a physical table, a physical room out there?

Of course.

But importantly, they are not of the same sort as the simulation. The simulation is a sensory, experienced construction produced by the brain to stand in for whatever realstuff is actually out there.

But maybe, just maybe, Elon doesn’t think there is anything real, that is anything other than simulation, out there. Maybe he doesn’t think physical stuff exists unless it’s created/simulated by a mind. Or a Mind.

In other words, maybe what Elon is guilty of is not bad math, but idealist philosophy.

Except—somewhere among the billions of simulated realities, he thinks there is one “base reality”. So strike that. We’re back to bad math.

The New Design Argument

As a matter of fact, if we step back, we see that the claim that we live inside a simulation created by some outside being is little more than the 21st century version of the Design Argument for God’s existence.

And like the Design Argument, it is not a logical argument at all, but an analogy.

And the analogy is this: like the characters that exist inside the virtual realities of our popular games, perhaps we too live inside a virtual reality created by some intelligent being or beings.

Well, it’s a thought. How do we evaluate its likelihood?4

Not the way Elon tries to do it.

Like the Design argument, its strength lies in misunderstanding what is going on when we know the world. If you buy into the core beliefs of supernaturalism, you might find the Design analogy compelling because it fits your worldview and your understanding of it. If you don’t buy into those beliefs, you will find the whole thing silly.

The original design argument drew its inspiration from the invention of clocks. These newfangled time-telling mechanisms impressed people during the middle ages because clocks operated automatically—at least until the spring needed to be rewound.

And this led to an idea: maybe earth is just one big clock designed by God. After all, every clock we know of is designed by an outside clockmaker: maybe the physical world was designed by an outside maker as well.

In Elon’s version, he would postulate billions and billions of clocks, as if large numbers made the analogy more convincing. Or more probable.

“There is only one chance in a billion that the earth is not a clock.”

Sorry Elon. This is math illiteracy.

Simulations, Simulations

Notice that the observation that humans might eventually create simulations that seem just like the real world is not something that matters much. It is, of course, where the 21st century version of the analogy gets its start, but the analogy doesn’t require that humans ever successfully create a convincing virtual world.5

Now, if we could create virtual worlds that actually contained sentient physical beings like us (rather than just fictional simulations of such), that would be both impressive and miraculous. If we could ever become such gods, well then others might have done so before us, and others before them.

But here’s the thing about simulations: they are simulations. They stand in for real things (even if fictional) and are not actually what they presumably simulate.

And we know this well, because hominids have been creating simulations for tens of thousands of years, starting with cave paintings and carvings.

A drawing of an object is a simulation of that object.

Horses on cave walls were simulations of horses, for all we know convincing enough to early hominids to make them believe the painting could control the living horse.

Perhaps a prehistoric Elon Musk looked at the Lascaux cave paintings and wondered if he and his tribe were themselves painted on the wall of some great cave somewhere, under the watchful eye of a celestial god. (Only one chance in whatever it wasn’t so.)

Paintings, frescoes, sculptures, carvings and masks were for thousands of years our chief form of simulating reality. And our simulations got better and better over the centuries. Painters got good at simulating at creating realistic pictures. Then we invented photography, followed by motion pictures, movies with sound, television, computer games and, today, 3D virtual reality.

But so far, none of our simulations of real things have ever turned into real thingsthemselves, at least not in the same sense of existence.

There is of course a secondary sense in which a cartoon character like Mickey Mouse has real existence, at least culturally. But Mickey Mouse has never become a blood and bones biological being in the sense that we are.6 Nor does anyone expect this to happen—unless they are mentally ill.

Yet advocates of the simulation hypothesis seem to believe that if only we can make cartoon Mickey’s world realistic enough to become indistinguishable from reality, and do the same for Mickey’s virtual body—presto! He will become a real, experiencing physical being, just like us.

Somewhere, somehow, at some point in perfecting the illusion, magic will happen.

That’s right.

This is magical, supernatural thinking. A belief quite literally in picture magic. Call it “simulation” magic.

The Simulation Inside Us

There is also an intellectual confusion going on here about what reality is.

What is being confused with reality is the simulation (vision, sound, touch, taste, smell) of the world which our brain creates to “stand in” for the world. This biologically-created simulation, however, is inside us. We are not inside it.

Now, there is something important to note about the biologically-created simulation happening inside us: it is computational in nature, composed of objects with properties and information that can be sliced and diced. Thus our brains provide us with a simulation of the world which is “knowable”—and indeed we can’t “know” anything which is not simulation for this precise reason.7

But if the simulation—all simulations—are actually inside us, product of our brains, then it follows that we (the biological beings producing the simulation) cannot be inside it (though of course we can put a representation of ourselves into it). We are necessarily on the outside hosting the simulation on the inside, just as we are necessarily outside any art or craft or motion picture or computer game which is triggering a brain simulation of reality within us.

Which presents us with another way to look at how ridiculous Elon’s logic is here:

Human brains have been creating these realistic simulations of reality (which we almost always naively fail to distinguished from reality) for millions of years, and millions of years before us the brains of other species have been doing the same.

Long before motion pictures, long before Pong, these realistic simulations of the physical world have been in existence. Again, I’m referring here to the sensual experiences we each have every day, experiences created by our brains and interpreted to be the world existing around us. Recall what I wrote earlier,

When I see an orange on the table, my brain creates my experience—the roundness, the color, the citric smell and so on. These orange properties are produced by my brain to create a virtual reality “orange” which stands in for the physical whateverlying on the table.

Not only that, in similar fashion my brain created the table, the room, everything.

The simulation is inside me.

It’s my creation.

In what rational sense can this be conceived as evidence that some other species on some other planet has imagined earth and all its species into existence as simulations in their own brains, in their own computer programs?

At best, it is an off the wall brain-fart analogy, a silly “what if?”

What if???

It boils down to this: What if I’m trapped in a story someone else is telling?

After all, millions maybe billions of stories have been told. If there are aliens elsewhere, quintillions of stories have been told.

Wow! The odds that I’m nothing but a character in a story must be immense.

The more stories I can imagine being told or enacted somewhere, somehow the more certain it must be that I don’t have independent existence, I’m just a character in a story not my own.

“…the odds that we’re in base reality is one in billions. Tell me what’s wrong with that argument? … Is there a flaw in that argument? … There’s a one in billion chance that this is base reality.”

We tell stores. We tell stories about others. What if they are trapped in our stories?

What if we only exist in someone else’s story?

Now imagine billions of stories—suddenly the off the wall brain-fart analogy magically acquires high probability in the minds of math-illiterates.

But the stories are so detailed!

They have moving pictures, and the pictures look and move just like us! Therefore they are living, breathing biological beings just like us—trapped in the computer story.

Uh-oh, we must be too!

Now, on top of all this silliness, Elon also believes that minds can be downloaded to a hard drive to achieve immortality8 (by “download” he doesn’t mean “writing books” either).

By definition, his is a supernatural worldview.9

Behind all his nonsense is the gullible belief that mind is primary, that mind must come before matter; that the other way around is unthinkable.

And Elon “proves” it with brain-fart math.

Footnotes

2

The idea is not original. Elon apparently got it (directly or indirectly) from the Oxford philosopher Nick Bostrom. I’ll write about him in a separate article.

3

Elon Musk, 2016. My transcription from YouTube video of Musk at Code Conference 2016

4

How do you calculate the likelihood of the Design Argument being true? You can’t. And this is because it’s just an analogy, a metaphor, a What-if? Do you have a supernatural worldview? Then you’ll calculate the probability that God or something like God created the physical world at 100%. Do you have a natural worldview? The probability becomes zero. And this is because the Design Argument is not evidence or argument at all, but rather a necessary corollary of holding a supernatural worldview. If mind came first, then physical stuff must be its design and creation. And if physical stuff came first, it can’t be the creation or design of any mind.

5

After all it’s an analogy, not an empirical observation. This is why Elon can’t construct a legitimate math problem to calculate the odds.

6

The actor in that Mickey Mouse costume at Disney World doesn’t count.

7

Fortunately, empiricism provides a method for getting around this limitation. Scientists falsify what they believe they know by careful doing in the world (and by meticulous noting of results): in this way beliefs get tested in competition against alternates and get judged by usefulness. Scientific knowledge is thus a simulation (standing in for the world) which gets consciously tested and improved to be more and more useful. Thus the relationship between the world and scientific knowledge is forever pragmatic: what works best we say is true (as long as the model is internally coherent). This is a continuation and extension of how earthly organisms deploy consciousness. It evolved into a practical stand-in for the physical world, one constructed by the brain and used to improve its decision-making. This is accomplished by creating and modifying memories, and thus connections between neurons which can impact future actions.

9

This is an infantile supernaturalism which doesn’t invoke God but rather pretends that super-powerful aliens out there in the cosmos (somewhere) created us and our physical reality. It’s not a mindful supernaturalism constructed over centuries of religious thought about the concept of God and ex nihilo creation. Rather, it mindlessly replaces God with powerful aliens living in “base reality” (who created their base reality?) who, Elon speculates, might have created our reality as a way to entertain themselves. Infantile supernaturalism.

Posted in Uncategorized | Leave a comment

Defining Naturalism the Right Way

[Post at Preface to Atheism, Feb 19, 2024. I should probably have titled it “Defining Naturalism the Best Way.”]

In a previous post, “What is Naturalism?”, I quoted William H Halverson’s A Concise Introduction to Philosophy, Fourth Edition, 1981 (Random House, NY). Today I want to return to Halverson and focus again on his presentation of naturalism as a world view. In doing so, I want to focus on a fundamental mistake in how naturalism has traditionally been presented.

In chapter 57, Halverson (writing “from the point of view of a convinced advocate of the view in question”) describes naturalism as claiming, “In the beginning, matter.” In contrast, he points out, supernaturalism claims, “In the beginning, God.” (I quoted this in “What is Naturalism?”)1

More broadly (though Halverson doesn’t say this) supernaturalism states, “In the beginning, mind, consciousness or intelligence.” The most popular versions of the supernatural world view eagerly call this God, but this move isn’t universal.

The main takeaway: naturalism and supernaturalism are competing factual claims about the history of existence. Naturalism says, originally there was physical stuff and then living organisms evolved (on earth, at least), and then some living organisms evolved to have consciousness. (The publication of Darwin’s On the Origin of Speciesin the 19th century reinvigorated naturalism, because it demonstrated that the forms of species could have come about without the application of intelligence from outside.)

It also highlights a central element of naturalism: consciousness (consequently mind and intelligence) is something produced by the brains of organisms. Not produced necessarily by all organisms, but by those with an adequate collection of neurons (details to follow as scientists do their work.) Therefore, if naturalism is correct, consciousness was not around at the beginning but arrived on the scene later.

By default, this entails atheism. It means that God’s sort of existence, which is bodiless mind or consciousness, was not around in the beginning. Such is the heart of naturalism, and it’s why I write so much about it here. Naturalism really is preface to atheism.

In opposition, supernaturalism asserts that, yes, consciousness may have arrived in organisms like us later on, but this was possible only because an originalConsciousness was present all along. Indeed, the original Consciousness created the physical world. In the beginning, God.

I want you to see the important of stating the difference between naturalism and supernaturalism in this way. It makes clear that the debate is over factual & historical claims. It is a debate over what happened when, as well as a debate over where consciousness is. Importantly, it’s a difference of opinion that can be adjudicated by examining evidence.

Bedeviled Naturalism

But Halverson’s presentation of naturalism in A Concise Introduction to Philosophy, in my opinion, has a fatal flaw; a mistake which bedevils advocates of naturalism to this day. And bedevil is the right word here. The flaw sneaks into naturalism a fundamental premise belonging to supernaturalism. It allows a supernatural devil (in the form of consciousness) to slither about in naturalism’s garden.

To see this, let’s look carefully at the relevant passages in his book:

“Naturalism asserts, first, that the primary constituents of reality are material entities. By this I do not mean that only material entities exist; I am not denying the reality—the real existence—of such things as hopes, plans, behavior, language, logical inferences, and so on. What I am asserting, however, is that anything that is real is, in the last analysis, explicable as a material entity or as a form or function or action of a material entity. Theism says, “In the beginning, God;” naturalism says, “In the beginning, matter.” If the theoretical goal of science—an absolutely exhaustive knowledge of the natural world—were to be achieved, there would remain no reality of any other kind about which we might still be ignorant. The “ultimate realities,” according to naturalism, are not the alleged objects of the inquiries of theologians; they are the entities that are the objects of investigation by chemists, physicists, and other scientists. To put the matter very simply: materialism is true.”2

Halverson’s naturalist next goes on to say that naturalism also holds “determinism is true” and that “to be is to be some place, some time.”

“Naturalism asserts, second, that what happens in the world is theoretically explicable without residue in terms of the internal structures and the external relations of these material entities. The world is, to use an inadequate metaphor, like a gigantic machine whose parts are so numerous and whose processes are so complex that we have, thus far, been able to achieve only a partial and fragmentary understanding of how it works. In principle, however, everything at occurs is ultimately explicable in terms of the properties and relations of the particles of which matter is composed. Once again, the point may be stated simply: determinism is true.”

“It follows from what I have said that the categories of space and time are categories of great importance of naturalism—are in fact, ontological categories. If you cannot locate something in space and time, or if you cannot understand it as a form or function of some entity or entities located in space and time, then you simply cannot say anything intelligible about it. To be is to be some place, some time.3

In these passages, I have emphasized the word “explicable” for a reason. This is the devil I mentioned earlier.

Not Halverson’s Fault

The devil is not Halverson’s fault. He merely presents naturalism as 20th century advocates have commonly misunderstood it. For example, Britannica.com says,

“Naturalism presumes that nature is in principle completely knowable. There is in nature a regularity, unity, and wholeness that implies objective laws, without which the pursuit of scientific knowledge would be absurd.”4

There is so much wrong with this that one almost doesn’t know where to begin.

Let start at the end, the assumption that without “objective laws” that “the pursuit of scientific knowledge would be absurd.” Well, it’s a claim. Yet the pursuit of science is unaffected by this question of where scientific laws exist. Whether they exist “out there” in the external world or whether they exist “in here” in human consciousness, science progresses all the same.

The lack of “out there” existence for our scientific conclusions might seem “absurd” to someone committed to a supernatural world view, but in fact it’s quite sensible. Thoughts, conclusions, understandings are all “in here” phenomena. Like all aspect of consciousness, human knowledge exists to “stand in” for the external physical world. But stand in is all knowledge ever does. It does not and cannot become “factual” in the external world.

Let me repeat: our scientific understanding of matter and energy stands in for the external world around us. It is a careless mistake to conflate scientific understanding of the world for the nature of the world. If you commit this error, you’ve inserted an element of human consciousness which exist in here and placed it out there—you’ve conflated subjective reality with objective reality.

If we dig down, we discover that the underlying fault here is the unquestioned assumption that organisms perceive the world through their senses, and that any resulting knowledge is objective (i.e. an aspect of the external natural world) rather than subjective (i.e. an aspect of human consciousness). Since sense sensations and meaning sensations are aspects of consciousness, this inevitably entangles human consciousness with the physical world around us, vitiating naturalism by inserting consciousness where it does not exist.

We need to rescue the world view of naturalism from this bedevilment so that everyone benefits from clearer thinking (whether naturalist or supernaturalist).

Indeed, Britannica.com does the opposite, turning naturalism into nothing more than the meaningless declaration “everything is natural.”

“While naturalism has often been equated with materialism, it is much broader in scope. Materialism is indeed naturalistic, but the converse is not necessarily true. Strictly speaking, naturalism has no ontological preference; i.e., no bias toward any particular set of categories of reality: dualism and monism, atheism and theism, idealism and materialism are all per se compatible with it. So long as all of reality is natural, no other limitations are imposed. Naturalists have in fact expressed a wide variety of views, even to the point of developing a theistic naturalism.”5

This is worthless.6

Explicibility and Perception

Perhaps it’s viable to view the common but confused presentation of naturalism as oneof several possible varieties which fall under the meta philosophy of naturalism—albeit deeply flawed. Fortunately, there are other variations under the meta philosophy, versions which excise explicability, thus restoring coherence, and also eliminating determinism (since determinism results from the desire for explicability “without residue”7).

We have sound biological & evolutionary reasons for excising explicability from being foundational. These include Hume’s observations about the problem of induction and of course, most importantly, Darwin’s On the Origin of Species8 which undoubtedly influenced William James’ ideas about pragmatism. These also include the rejection of scientific realism, which is necessitated by the biological understanding that species (including us, of course) have no actual method of perceiving9 the world. We are left with scientific pragmatism to replace scientific realism. (But these are topics for future Preface articles.)

Instead, let me continue to focus on the logical reason for removing explicability from the definition of naturalism.

Explicability commits naturalism to the proposition that organisms, through sensations and consciousness, can perceive the physical world as it is. This commitment to perception relies on the assumption that consciousness and the “outside” physical world are a two-way street. On one side of the street, neurons in the brain produce consciousness. (A necessary assumption for naturalism, and amply supported by the evidence we have.)

But on the other side of the street, somehow, consciousness interacts with the outside physical world which we are sensing, so that it can be “perceived.”

It would not be a problem if the assertion were that the two-way interaction occurs between consciousness and the brain: brain producing consciousness and consciousness modifying neurons in return. But the claim of explicability alters the nature of the two-way street: it asserts that consciousness, in its sensual form (i.e., the senses) is a perception of the outside world, and therefore an interaction with whatever physical stuff is.

But how can this be? Logically, it implies compatibility between the sensations of consciousness and the physical world. This is just plain mystical: in the end it means that the physical world (exclusive of neurons in the brain) must have a nature which interacts with and is compatible with consciousness.

If we accept this, we are no longer advocating naturalism or physicalism. So advocates of naturalism should reject this mess.

Instead, advocate of naturalism (thinking logically) should limit the interaction between consciousness and the physical world to the realm of the brain’s neurons: there alone is where interaction between matter and mind, stuff and sensation, “objective” and “subjective” occurs. The brain produces consciousness and consciousness in turn modifies the brain. Consciousness never exists outside this limited interaction. It’s a tool the brain uses to improve itself, and that is that.

Let me summarize my argument in a different form. Per Halverson, explicabilityasserts that human thoughts can tap into the actual “properties and relations of the particles of which matter is composed.” But this is based on the unnatural assumption that properties and relations can be found in the physical world.

But wait: properties and relations are the native language of consciousness. So explicability misleads us into asserting that the native language of consciousness is something that we can find in the physical world as we interact with it.

Such a position is not naturalism. It’s pan-psychism or supernaturalism.

Again, if interaction between elements of consciousness and the physical world is constrained to the brain and its neurons, it poses no problem for naturalism. But allow compatibility between consciousness and physical stuff to occur outside of neurons in the brain, and you’ve jumped out of naturalism into it’s negation.

You’ve allowed the devil into your natural garden.

1

William H. Halverson, A Concise Introduction to Philosophy, 4th Edition, New York, 1967-1981, Random House, page 424.

2

Ibid.

3

Ibid.

5

Ibid.

6

Interestingly, if you replace the word “naturalism” with “science” then the quote makes sense. Has Britannica equated science with “methodological naturalism” and forgotten that philosophical naturalism (the meta philosophy of naturalism) even exists?

7

More on this in future posts.

9

In future posts I will outline the biological case against organisms perceiving the world around themselves. The concept of perception has been scientifically debunked, but most philosophers haven’t caught up yet.

Posted in Uncategorized | Leave a comment

Roundess & What is Real

[Post at Preface to Atheism, Sept 16, 2023.]

It’s natural to assume that what we see when we open our eyes is what the world looks like, that we see it as is. Sure, there may be more to it than we see, especially on a micro level, but we see the actual world out there. This assumption is what philosophers call perceptual realism (though it has other names, such as naive realism).

Bertrand Russell, in his book, The Problems of Philosophy1, exposed a few of the problems with perceptual realism.

Consider a round dining table. Imagine that we are comfortably sitting in a chair beside the table. Looking at the table from our vantage point, it is likely that we perceive immediately that the tabletop is round. But how? From where we sit, the tabletop does not actually have a round shape.

This is the problem: how can we perceive the table as round if the image of the table coming through our eyes is not round? Sitting at the table, in fact, it appears oval. It would only appear round if our eyes were located at the ceiling directly above the table—a viewpoint we almost never actually have.

Yet we immediately register the table as round.

Presumably, roundness is one of the properties of the table. But how does our brain pick up this property from the table? How does our brain know it is round?

We can even ask, is the physical tabletop really round or is roundness something our brain is (so to speak) bringing to the table?

Or, as philosophers like to put it, is the table’s roundness real?

The Real Question

Whenever philosophers (or anyone for that matter) asks if something is real, what they are actually asking is a different question: where does something exist? The philosopher’s question, Is roundness real? is, in other words, the scientist’s question, Where does roundness exist?

There are basically only a couple of places where something might exist.

First, it might exist in the “physical” mind-independent world we see around (outside/inside of) us. Perhaps it exists in this world in a manner easy to detect, or perhaps it exists undetected or even undetectable. Something might also exist within organisms which are within this mind-independent world, perhaps even within the structure of neurons in the brains of such organisms.

Most philosophers would consider something existing in any of the above locations to be “real”.

Second, something may also exist “in our mind”—that is, in our thoughts, feelings, or imagination. If something “only” exists in our minds philosophers would say it is not “real.” Realism, to the philosopher, means believing that something exists in the firstlocation. If we believe that something only exists in the second location, it is a rejection of realism vis-a-vis that something.

Of course, something might exist in both places. And in fact this is a common position most people (including philosophers) take.

It is my position that something never exists in both places. Either it exists in the mind-independent, observer-independent physical world, or it exists in the mind of an observer. Never both.

With one caveat: Observers are organisms. And organisms exist in the mind-independent world. In this sense, naturally, the minds of organisms (which are produced by neurons in the organism’s body) necessarily also exist in the mind-independent physical world. But there is never double-existence. Something which exists within the neurobiologically-produced consciousness of an organism doesn’t also exist outside that neurbiologically-produced consciousness.

So if we are talking about something like the roundness of a tabletop, it is my contention that that property of roundness either exists out there in the table (the mind-independent world) or it exists in here in the neurobiological consciousness (mind) produced in the brains of organisms like us.

I hope this clarifies why I think the scientific question, Where does something exist? is preferable to the philosophical question, Is something real?

Where is Roundness?

So where does the roundness of our dining table exist?

Let’s recap the issue:

If roundness is out there in the physical world, how do we perceive an object’s roundness if we never see it round? How does an object so quickly convey its roundness to us?

Well, some objects don’t. The earth we stand on is round, but we don’t perceive that (okay, maybe if we are astronauts/cosmonauts out in space). Only when an object is small enough for us to see it from the proper angle, do we actually see it as round.

So roundness is not conveyed to us by the objects we see. Our brains are inferringroundness.2

And this is even more obvious when we consider that round objects are never perfectly round. We perceive oranges as round, but they are not perfectly round. Our dining table is not perfectly round. Our earth is not perfectly round. And neither are coins.

If something is not perfectly round, is it round?

Well, our brain says it is. And then, on further examination, our brain says it is not perfectly round.

So where does roundness exist?

If we approach this question as scientists, then we are going to look for a biological mechanism for collecting information from the world around us.

Let’s imagine we are sitting outside at night looking at the full moon. The information that the disk of the moon is round, how are we to pluck that from the sky?

Our retinas sample photons which have bounced off the moon from the sun. What do those photons know about the roundness of the moon? Do they carry information about the moon’s roundness with them to earth. Certainly not individually.

Collectively, we convince ourselves, at least together with the missing photons where moon is not, we assemble a picture of the moon’s roundness. But it’s a picture wecompose. Specifically, our brains compose it, and our brains create the information of the moon’s roundness in doing so. Photons know nothing about it.

What about Cameras?

Still, we might naively ask, how then can a camera (a brainless, non-digital camera, for instance) create a picture of the moon’s roundness? Where does the roundness information come from if not the photons captured by the camera?

But here, too, our brains create the roundness of the moon. This time it happens when we look at the photo from the camera.

If someone paints a full moon on canvas, it’s the same thing. When we look at the canvas our brains create the roundness of the painted moon, just as would happen if we were looking at the moon itself.

And then our brains note that the roundness is imperfect.

Our brains, of course, don’t just create roundness information about the moon. They create an entire moon object. This moon-object has properties, including hue, saturation, and brightness. It also has an edge forming the property of roundness.

The objectification of the visual field into objects with discernible properties and information seems to be an automatic activity of the human brain. I would go further and declare that all experiences—that is, all sensation created by the brain for the purpose of moving and acting within the world around us—by nature have location and meaning (so that the sensation can bring a call to action to the organism). This is why our sensations, our experiences, present us with information necessarily.3

A natural answer

Skeptical naturalism answers the question Where does roundness exist? by locating it in the simulacrum created by the brain as it produces our senses and knowledge.

This video4 which I linked to in a previous post demonstrates the point. Watch the video (before reading further)!

If you duteously tried to count the basketball throws as directed, your brain saturated your visual experience with objects needed for the task at hand: you see the basketball, you see the basketball players passing the basketball, maybe you see the players on the opposing team as well since passes from them shouldn’t count. These objects are essential to counting the basketball throws.

But you didn’t see the man in a gorilla suit object. Why not?

Your brain created the visual experience you needed for the task at hand; distractions were excluded from your vision because you had something tricky to concentrate on.

Afterwards, once you learned about the gorilla-suited man, your brain took note and “improved itself”—and I bet now your brain won’t allow you to unsee him the next time you watch the video. (Can you even fully concentrate on counting the throws once you know what’s really important about the scene?)

The question, then, is not whether the brain constructs our experiences. It absolutely constructs the objects and properties that we visualize. The question, rather, is this: are those objects and properties (such as roundness) located in one place or two places?

Are they located only in the neurobiological construction we call consciousness, or do they also have duplicates located in the mind-independent physical world?

I submit that the meta philosophy of naturalism5 is not consistent with saying objects and properties exist in both places. This is because the places—one mind-independent and one mind-dependent—are fundamentally different in type. And the meta philosophy of naturalism says that the second type is a neurobiological construction which shows up only after millions or billions of years.

Things produced by neurons in the brains of organisms can’t be equivalent to things predating the evolution of neurons—not at least under naturalism. (If you have a supernatural worldview, you will see it differently.)

I hope this gets at why I don’t think perceptual realism fits naturalism. And I believe the same will apply for scientific realism.

Footnotes

1

Bertrand Russell, The Problems of Philosophy, Oxford University Press, 1912.

In the future, I hope to write specifically about ideas Russell presents here—this post is not that. But my point about roundness comes directly from The Problems of Philosophy:

“The shape of the table is no better. We are all in the habit of judging as to the ‘real’ shapes of things, and we do this so unreflectingly that we come to think we actually see the real shapes. But, in fact, as we all have to learn if we try to draw, a given thing looks different in shape from every different point of view. If our table is ‘really’ rectangular, it will look, from almost all points of view, as if it had two acute angles and two obtuse angles. If opposite sides are parallel, they will look as if they converged to a point away from the spectator; if they are of equal length, they will look as if the nearer side were longer. All these things are not commonly noticed in looking at a table, because experience has taught us to construct the ‘real’ shape from the apparent shape, and the ‘real’ shape is what interests us as practical men. But the ‘real’ shape is not what we see; it is something inferred from what we see. And what we see is constantly changing in shape as we, move about the room; so that here again the senses seem not to give us the truth about the table itself, but only about the appearance of the table.” (1959 Edition, page 10)

2

Again, Russell in The Problems of Philosophy:

“Thus it becomes evident that the real table, if there is one, is not the same as what we immediately experience by sight or touch or hearing. The real table, if there is one, is not immediately known to us at all, but must be an inference from what is immediately known. Hence, two very difficult questions at once arise; namely, (1) Is there a real table at all? (2) If so, what sort of object can it be?” (1959 Edition, page 11)

3

In The Problems of Philosophy, Russell separates “sensations” from what he terms “sense data.” Whereas, I believe the brain constructs both in the same fashion, often at the same time. Thus sensations come with meaning for the organism (it’s an important aspect of their neurological construction). Here’s Russell’s take:

“Let us give the name of ‘sense-data’ to the things that are immediately known in sensation: such things as colours, sounds, smells, hardnesses, roughnesses, and so on. We shall give the name ‘sensation’ to the experience of being immediately aware of these things. Thus, whenever we see a colour, we have a sensation of the colour, but the colour itself is a sense-datum, not a sensation. The colour is that of which we are immediately aware, and the awareness itself is the sensation. It is plain that if we are to know anything about the table, it must be by means of the sense-data — brown colour, oblong shape, smoothness, etc. — which we associate with the table; but, for the reasons which have been given, we cannot say that the table is the sense-data, or even that the sense-data are directly properties of the table. Thus a problem arises as to the relation of the sense-data to the real table, supposing there is such a thing.” (1959 Edition, page 12)

It has never been clear to me where Russell thinks sense-data exists. I maintain that like all our sensations, sense-data is constructed by the brain using much the same mechanisms which create our other neurobiological experiences.

4

Learn more about this at theinvisiblegorilla.com

5

As stated in a previous post, the “meta philosophy of naturalism” is equivalent to a “meta scientific hypothesis” that the world has a history, and that this history includes, after billions of years, the evolution of living organisms on at least one planet in at least one solar system, and that on that planet at least one species evolved to have brains which produce neurobiological consciousness. Instances of this neurobiological consciousness constitute novel entities (e.g. visual, tactile, auditory sensations but also including information, conceptsand meanings) which never existed prior. (Roundness and other object properties are examples of such.) Because these novel entities never existed prior to the evolution of consciousness, an essential aspect of the hypothesis is that they exist only in consciousness, not in the mind-independent (consciousness-independent) world beyond.

Posted in Uncategorized | Leave a comment

John Shook’s analysis of Naturalism

[Third post on Preface to Atheism.]

John Shook is one of the leading philosophers of naturalism. My understanding is that he advocates for pragmatic naturalism (evidence: he edited a book with that title, and has published books about the pragmatists William James and John Dewey). My version of skeptical naturalism also leverages pragmatism (pragmatic empiricism, specifically).

But Shook will tell you that I am wrong, that naturalism simply can’t be combined with skepticism.

Let’s try to understand his point of view, which can be found here: http://www.naturalisms.org/science.htm

Shook explains that “There are six primary options when considering whether science yields knowledge about reality” and he goes through them one by one to evaluate whether or not they can be compatible with naturalism.

First on his list is skepticism (which, remember, I think biology forces on us, since there is no plausible biological method for organisms on earth to perceive the world as it is, and that what we mistake for perception is actually a construction by the brain treated as if it is the world—a stand-in).

Describing skepticism as a worldview, Shook writes

Reality cannot be known at all. All knowledge is impossible because of fatal flaws within any ways of attempted knowing. This option is usually called “Radical” or “Philosophical” Skepticism. This option is NOT the same as the ordinary skepticism of common sense, or the scientific skepticism that demands experimental evidence to have knowledge.”1

This is the essence of skepticism, although I do have a quibble with it. The claim is not that “all knowledge is impossible”—of course knowledge is possible! Organisms like us do tons of knowing! Rather the claim of philosophical (and academic) skepticism is that all knowledge of reality is impossible, where “reality” refers to the “mind-independent, observer-independent” physical world (where, of course, organisms like us who are observers, organisms with consciousness, exist).

By the word “reality”, we thus mean exclusive of the “observer” or “mind” aspect of organisms like us. Because after all consciousness is all about knowing. The point of radical or philosophical skepticism is that all this knowing is not knowing of the mind-independent, observer-independent aspect of reality: it’s knowing of a biologically created (brain-created) stand-in which organisms employ pragmatically to navigate reality.

We will see that the reason Shook rejects skepticism as a basis for naturalism is because skepticism is incompatible with scientific realism, and Shook believes naturalism requires scientific realism to stand on. (This is the obvious point of disagreement—and later on when we talk about how to define naturalism, we’ll see that the disagreement carries on into that discussion, as one would expect.)

Let’s continue with Shooks six primary options.

The second one is

Reality only consists of what science cannot know about. There is another non-scientific way of understanding reality that should be trusted instead of science. Since science’s conclusions do not agree with this non-scientific way of understanding reality, science is completely untrustworthy.”

Not surprisingly, this is where mysticism, spiritualism, idealism, rationalism reside. In fact, here you will find the residences of a great many people today. It is not an option for naturalism.

Third, Shook gives us

Science is rarely able to give reliable knowledge about reality. Science can occasionally provide reliable knowledge, but only about a limited portion or aspect of reality.”

Here he breaks out two varieties. The first (3A) stresses pure reason (or religious intuition?) as a more reliable alternative to science. Here Shook includes “[m]ost types of Platonism, Idealism, Phenomenalism, and Phenomenology

Anti-Realism

More interesting is 3B. This is where Shook places anti-realism (the rejection of scientific realism).

“The scientific anti-realist has decided that none of arguments for Scientific Realism (the view that science does provide some genuine knowledge of reality) are convincing. In the 20th century, scientific anti-realists have preferred types of Empiricism (like Positivism‘s view that science can only describe patterns of phenomena), or Social Constructivism (the view that science’s claims are largely caused by cultural/political forces). Another type of empiricism is Instrumentalism, which holds that science can only give knowledge about directly or instrumentally observable entities.”

What Shook doesn’t list here is my preferred version of anti-realism: biological constructivism. There are other names for it: neurological constructivism, scientific constructivism, model-dependent realism come to mind.

That last (model-dependent realism) is from The Grand Design, a 2010 book by Stephen Hawking and Leonard Mlodinow.

According to the idea of model-dependent realism …, our brains interpret the input from our sensory organs by making a model of the outside world. We form mental concepts of our home, trees, other people, the electricity that flows from wall sockets, atoms, molecules, and other universes. These mental concepts are the only reality we can know. There is no model-independent test of reality.2

The neuroscientist György Buzsáki makes a related point in the June 2022 issue of Scientific American. Buzsáki rejects what he calls the traditional “outside-in framework” because it relies on an outside observer (the objective scientist). He provides an example of someone “seeing” a flower; from the outside-in framework

A stimulus—the image of a flower—reaches the eyes, and the brain responds by causing neurons to fire. This theory is plausible only with the involvement of an “experimenter” to observe and establish a relation between the flower and the neuronal responses it induces. Absent the experimenter, neurons in the sensory cortex do not “see” the flower.3

Instead, Buzsáki proposes an “inside-out framework.”

The alternative, inside-out theory does away with the experimenter. It presumes instead that we come to understand the external world by taking actions—moving a flower, for instance—to learn about an object. To accomplish this task, inputs from action-initiating neurons combine with sensory inputs to provide an understanding of the object’s size shape and other attributes. A meaningful picture arises, allowing the neurons to “see” the flower.4

The outside-in framework relies on the assumption of scientific realism, whereas the inside-out framework does not. In similar fashion, Hawking’s model-dependent realism bypasses the need to assume scientific realism.

Donald Hoffman, who I mentioned in a previous post, is an earlier (and more forceful) proponent of the idea that our brains construct what we see.5 (Seems to me, Hawking and Mlodinow were knowledgable of modern currents in neuroscience and developed their model-dependent realism accordingly.)

Realism vs Realism

The reader might wonder why I include model-dependent realism as an example of anti-realism? How can a type of realism be a type of anti-realism?

Blame philosophers.

In philosophy there are two quite different “primary” meanings of the term realism. The first is the assertion that the physical world exists independent of mind (often referred to as belief in a mind-independent or observer-independent reality). This meaning of realism stands opposed to idealism. Stephen Hawking and Leonard Mlodinow mean this sort of realism when describing model-dependent realism. They assert that there is indeed a physical reality—it’s just that we can’t actually know it as it is, so we construct models which stand in for it.

The other (and more common) meaning of realism in philosophy is the specific assertion of scientific realism—but beware because there is a grand philosophical tradition of confounding these two realism. Scientific realism necessarily embraces the first sort of (mind-independent) realism. But so do most anti-realists (those who reject scientific realism—I’ve argued, for example, that scientific realism fails to take mind-independent realism seriously enough.)

Scientific realism tacks on two additional claims.

Semantically, [scientific] realism is committed to a literal interpretation of scientific claims about the world. In common parlance, realists take theoretical statements at “face value”. According to realism, claims about scientific objects, events, processes, properties, and relations (I will use the term “scientific entity” as a generic term for these sorts of things henceforth), whether they be observable or unobservable, should be construed literally as having truth values, whether true or false.6

And the second is this:

Epistemologically, [scientific] realism is committed to the idea that theoretical claims (interpreted literally as describing a mind-independent reality) constitute knowledge of the world. This contrasts with skeptical positions which, even if they grant the metaphysical and semantic dimensions of realism, doubt that scientific investigation is epistemologically powerful enough to yield such knowledge, or, as in the case of some antirealist positions, insist that it is only powerful enough to yield knowledge regarding observables. The epistemological dimension of realism, though shared by realists generally, is sometimes described more specifically in contrary ways…. Amidst these differences, however, a general recipe for realism is widely shared: our best scientific theories give true or approximately true descriptions of observable and unobservable aspects of a mind-independent world.7

Model-dependent realism rejects this for a far more pragmatic view of scientific theories, one

which accepts that reality can always be interpreted in a number of different ways, and focuses on how well our models of the world do at describing the observed phenomena. It claims that it is meaningless to talk about the “true reality” of the model. The only meaningful thing is the usefulness of the model.8

Like biological constructivism, model-dependent realism asserts the existence of a mind/observer-independent reality, but denies that we can know it as it is. (In short, this is naturalism based on skepticism.) Hawking and Mlodinow arrived at this conclusion based on their understanding of modern neuroscience, where it is clear that organisms have no way to perceive the world and so must construct a model of it.

And science is a conceptual continuation of that construction.

Back to John Shook

We left off with John Shook placing anti-realism under category 3B, a variant of

Science is rarely able to give reliable knowledge about reality. Science can occasionally provide reliable knowledge, but only about a limited portion or aspect of reality.”

According to Shook, “These empiricisms [the variations of anti-realism] can’t develop into viable naturalisms, and instead collapse into 3A options such as idealism or phenomenalism.”

But I think we can see clearly now that 3B is the wrong place for most versions of anti-realism—certainly this is the case for model-dependent realism and biological constructivism. Both properly fall under Shook’s category of skepticism. This is because, for reasons of neurobiology, both embrace skepticism about our ability to know reality as it actually is.

Both assert that this is not a problem for science.

Both insist on a mind-independent world which is primary and existed before organisms like us evolved into being.

Both therefore embrace the meta-philosophy of naturalism, and do so via skepticism.

Conclusion: John Shooks says naturalism can’t be based on skepticism9, but I think we’ve shown that he is mistaken.

Footnotes

1

This and the following John Shook quotes come from http://www.naturalisms.org/science.htm

2

Stephen Hawking & Leonard Mlodinow, The Grand Design, 2010, as quoted here: https://www.thoughtco.com/what-is-model-dependent-realism-2699404

3

This and the previous quote are from “Constructing the World from Inside Out” by György Buzsáki, Scientific American, June 2022.

4

ibid

6

Quote from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/scientific-realism/ section 1.2, The Three Dimensions of Realist Commitment.

7

ibid

9

As noted at the beginning, Skepticism is primary worldview 1. Shook says “Only three of the 6 primary worldviews can lead to kinds of naturalism. They are:

4. Science is able to give increasingly reliable knowledge about reality. There may be other ways besides science for knowing reality, but those ways are not better than science. One variety can be a kind of naturalism: 4B. Synoptic Monism(one kind of ultimate reality that is knowable in different ways).

5. Science is the only source of knowledge about reality. The only type of knowledge is scientific knowledge. However, some of reality consists of entities that cannot be known by science, simply because science is not designed to provide knowledge about these entities. Two interesting varieties: 5A. Perspectival Realism (experience is a perspective on reality but not itself knowable), and 5B. Transcendent Realism (some natural reality forever escapes science).

6. Reality only consists of what science knows about. Only what can be known by science really exists. Two interesting varieties: 6A. Current Scientific Exclusivism(reality only consists of what current science knows now), and 6B. Scientific Exclusivism(reality only consists of what perfected science would know).”

http://www.naturalisms.org/science.htm

 

·
Posted in Uncategorized | Leave a comment

What is naturalism?

[This was my second post on Preface to Atheism, Aug 23, 2023.]

In my first post I talked about my sudden flip to a natural worldview when I was young. I mentioned that I didn’t call what I believed naturalism at the time because (thanks to the influence of Zeno) I had become completely skeptical about our ability to know the world as it is.

Back then when I read descriptions of naturalism, it was clear that it involved the rejection of skepticism and embrace of something (though I didn’t know it then) called scientific realism1, or the embrace of determinism outright.

But turns out, this is because 20th century advocates of naturalism got distracted from its essential point.

In A Concise Guide to Philosophy, William H. Halverson put his finger on the essential point: “Theism says, “In the beginning, God;” naturalism says, “In the beginning, matter.”2

Notice that when put this way, supernaturalism and naturalism are factual, historical claims about the world. Supernaturalism says that mind (or consciousness or spirit or something non-physical) existed, and then brought the physical world into existence. Naturalism says the opposite. Each, in fact, serves as a kind of scientific meta-hypothesis.

Naturalism, as scientific meta-hypothesis, claims this: the history of the world (where “world” means everything, all universes if there are multiple, and any/all pre-universe, pre-big bang states) is such that at first there existed no consciousness or thoughts. Then, on at least one planet in at least one solar system, living organisms evolved. Then at least one species on that planet evolved brains which produce consciousness including thoughts.

Another way of putting this is that the meta-hypothesis states that consciousness is a biological phenomenon and that this biological phenomenon simply did not exist (and cannot exist) until organisms with bodies and brains capable of producing it evolved into existence.

In other words, naturalism in its essence is not just a scientific/historical claim, it is a biological claim about the nature and origin of mind and consciousness (which broadly I will refer to as mind-stuff). If mind-stuff has a biological origin and nature, then mind-stuff did not exist until at least one planet formed capable of supporting life.

One obvious thing about the meta-hypothesis of naturalism is that it entails atheism. If thoughts and consciousness are biological, then without a body there can be no thoughts, no consciousness, no qualia.3 Such stuff can’t exist until organisms with bodies and brains evolved, therefore we know that disembodied mind or disembodied consciousness cannot be the origin of the world.

If the hypothesis of naturalism is true, atheism follows.

Skeptical Naturalism

An important scientific task becomes identifying the mind-stuff produced by brains and moving it to the biological consciousness side of the ledger—that is, making sure we don’t inadvertently leave mind-stuff on the “physical” side and thus confuse (that is, inadvertently abandon) the naturalistic hypothesis without realizing it.4

As part of this effort, I’m going to focus skeptical naturalism.

The skeptical naturalist hypothesis holds that all elements of knowing are aspects of biological consciousness. This moves a lot more stuff to the “mind” or consciousness side of the ledger than is usually done by advocates of naturalism. I take this position because I believe the biological and neurobiological evidence forces it.

The specific hypothesis is this: animals are unable to perceive the world, so consciousness evolved as a substitute for the world.

For example, vision (everything that we or other animals “see”) is a substitute—not a perception of the world as it is, but a stand-in created by our brains and used to better navigate the world.

I think this becomes obvious when we look at the neuroscience of vision. Whenever we open our eyes, we think we see the world around us, but our bodies and brains actually have no way to do that. Instead, what our retinas do is sample photons. These photons are particles of light which bounced off physical stuff in the world, but they are not the objects and things they bounced off—those things our retinas never see.

Our eyes detect photons, but we see visual scenes.

In short, brains evolved to construct scenes based on hints from photons. I will address this in more detail in the future, showing how optical illusions prove vision is a construction by the brain. But for the moment a few examples may suffice.

The first is a demonstration of the brain modifying color to enhance the usefulness of a visual scene. (It should be noted that photons don’t have colors. Our brains create color to aid in object tracking. The example shows that color is not the perception of wavelength.)

The second is an example of the brain constructing movement where we know there is none. (Optical illusions are situations where the brain’s rules for constructing vision end up not being reliable.5)

Watch this video and see if you can correctly count how many times the players wearing white pass the basketball. (This demonstrates that the brain’s purpose when constructing vision depends on the organism’s goal at hand. If you go back and re-experience the identical situation—which, conveniently, videos allow us to do—but with different goals, or after learning from the first experience, your brain constructs a different visual experience.)

So instead of perceiving the world, brains of organisms evolved to create a virtual world—this is what vision and sound and all other senses are: virtual creations by the brain (sensual consciousness) which evolved as a stand-in so that organisms can successfully navigate the world around.

To repeat: the physical world can’t be perceived, but organisms can interact with it. On earth, these interactions led to brains evolving the best possible alternative—a virtual reality composed of sensations which can be perceived and known and employed as an almost real-time substitute.

This is what vision is. This is what hearing is. This is what touching, tasting, smelling are. They are simulacra created on the fly by brains of organisms in order to navigate the world.

Simulacra are so well done that we mistake them for the world.

Getting back to skeptical naturalism, there is an additional hypothesis that if we can’t perceive the world, we can’t know the world.

And that it doesn’t matter.

It doesn’t matter because we have the brain’s simulacra to work with. Best of all, the simulacra have built-in hooks for knowledge—because, meanings and concepts are themselves simulacra.

In humans (and probably most complex organisms) the brain’s various simulacra are integrated into a more or less coherent whole, which I refer to as a simulacrum. In us, the simulacrum includes not just our various senses, but also objectifications (objects and properties) along with our understandings, our knowledge of those objectifications.

More on this later.

Footnotes

1

You can read about why I reject scientific realism in my article at atheology.com, Skepticism about Scientific Realism.

2

William H. Halverson, A Concise Guide to Philosophy, Fourth Edition, p 424. Halverson goes on to assert that naturalism also says, “determinism is true.” I believe this is a result of conflating the physical world with our understanding of the physical world; to be consistent with the meta philosophy of naturalism, advocates should diligently avoid conflating mind-independent reality with knowledge (which, to say the least, is not mind-independent).

3

Because spiritual entities are “non-physical,” under naturalism they are classed as biological phenomenon. This is because the meta-hypothesis is that the entire “consciousness” class of entities are biological experiences produced by brains of organisms. Supernaturalism, of course, sees things differently and makes the entire class primary, not dependent on matter or biology.

4

Of course, the supernatural meta hypothesis is always an option for scientists. I’m not asserting that naturalism’s meta hypothesis is required to do science, nor that science is committed to methodological naturalism. Rather, I am trying to clarify concepts and align naturalism with 21st century neuroscience to make it as useful as possible.

5

For more on this I recommend Donald Hoffman’s book, Visual Intelligence. “Hoffman explains that far from being a passive recorder of a preexisting world, the eye actively constructs every aspect of our visual experience.” (Of course it is the brain not the eye which does bulk of the constructing.) I will write more about Hoffman in the future.

 

Posted in Uncategorized | Leave a comment

Preface to Atheism

[Preface to Atheism is a blog I started on SubStack. What follows is the first post from Aug 18, 2023]

In this Substack, I will advocate atheism as entailed by the meta philosophy of naturalism rather than atheism based on doubt about God or religion. There’s nothing wrong with doubting God or religion, of course, but I hope to convince you that the benefits of atheism based on naturalism are immense and often overlooked by many atheists.

To an extent, this is because of my own history.

For the first 20 years of my life, I was a “student” of Christian Science—a 19th century New Age religion founded by Mary Baker Eddy. As a religion it was progressive for its time, a relatively feminist blend of spiritualism, Christianity, and philosophical idealism.

The philosophical idealism part of the mix is paramount to my story. You should understand that Christian Scientists reject dualism and embrace a monism in which mind—Divine Mind—is the only reality. Our individual minds are a reflection of Divine Mind, but if that reflection gets clouded we subject ourselves to sin, disease and death.

This is because our bodies are seen as the spiritual reflections of our thoughts. Correcting our thoughts so they properly reflect Divine Mind is how Christian Scientists attempt to cure the body (which is the primary goal of adherents).

This brief description of C.S. leaves a lot unexplained, and perhaps I’ll fill in more in a future post. Right now the focus is my own intellectual history, and the key element I want to convey is that as a child I grew up in a religion steeped in philosophical idealism.

But in 1974, at age 20, I became an atheist—not from doubting God’s existence but due to a sudden, unexpected flip in my brain to a natural framework.

(It was as if the very moment my brain perceived a new option possible, I flipped.)

Instead of a monism with mind (Divine or otherwise) primary, I flipped to one where physical matter was primary. It solved many problems (we will get to those in later posts).

At the time I didn’t know what to call my new worldview, so I settled on atheism—which I had grown up to think of as the “evil idea.” But notably determinism—another “evil idea” closely associated in my mind with atheism—did not flip to my new worldview. Determinism got excluded because mind and its explanations were, per my new framework, no longer primary.

I had a worldview that gave up God while excluding determinism. Did it really work?

I have spent most of my life trying to find out.

Zeno

My flip occurred because for years I struggled with the paradoxes of Zeno of Elea, particularly the Arrow paradox. My 9th grade English teacher, Miss Blumenstock, introduced me to Zeno and, once introduced, I couldn’t let it go.

However, one of the risks of learning philosophy in English class is that stuff may get garbled. That happened here.

For years I did not understand that Zeno presented the arrow’s movement as a paradoxintended to challenge contemporary thinking.

Instead, I misunderstood Zeno to have a theory of motion, specifically: that motion is not continuous as we naively suppose, but rather the result of an object jumping through a series of discrete locations one after the other. (For example, Zeno’s arrow would start in location A1 then be in location A2, next A3 and so on, and thus the arrow is never actually in movement between locations.)

But rather than presenting a theory of motion in which there is no actual movement, Zeno instead was asserting a paradox: if the arrow has a known location, it’s not moving; if it’s moving, it doesn’t have a known location.

In short, Zeno used paradoxes like the Arrow to throw in doubt our ability to know the world as it really is.

His paradoxes are particularly devastating for mathematics, for they demonstrate that formulas can’t be used to know reality; rather mathematics only pertain to “appearances”.

This distinction between appearance and reality comes from Parmenides, Zeno’s teacher, mentor, and (according to ancient rumor) lover.

Zeno’s paradoxes were intended to support Parmenides and to demonstrate that in attempting to know the world, we interface with how the world appears to us, not with actual reality (which Parmenides called “the One”), and that this discrepancy generates paradoxes which (according to Zeno1) apply even to our use of mathematics when we describe the world.

I believe Zeno was fundamentally correct.

Most importantly for today, modern philosophy has to take this mismatch between knowledge and reality seriously, or it stumbles.

Anyway, after five years of struggling with Zeno, I finally grasped the inevitability of Zeno’s mismatch between knowledge and the world. It was this new understanding which drove my brain flip after I turned 20.

The result was that in a moment I went from theism to atheism, from idealism to physicalism. I became an atheist without first having doubts about God’s existence.

Naturalism

I had flipped to a natural worldview, but I didn’t call it naturalism.

Why not?

Because in those days the definition of naturalism did not seem to be compatible with the inevitability of a mismatch between knowledge and the world. Even today, most definitions of naturalism embrace scientific realism (which is a denial of the mismatch) or else embrace something pretty close to scientific realism.

Still, if we back up and look at naturalism as a meta philosophy, this is where my worldview fits. And because naturalism as a meta philosophy entails atheism, the latter serves as a reasonable enough tag for my beliefs. But naturalism is the better tag.

Anyway, in 1974 I embraced physicalism and called myself an atheist—at the same time dismissing determinism. My new outlook was all about rejecting the primacy of mind, and as I saw it this rejection entailed not conflating the world with our understanding of the world.

I embraced the mismatch.

Since then, I’ve tried to understand if this was the right move. Is it sound? In Preface to Atheism, I’ll explain why I think it is.

Footnotes

1

This of course is my interpretation. Unfortunately Zeno’s writings do not survive, and all we have today are a few references by his intellectual opponents to a small subset of the paradoxes (9 out of 40+). Much of what we have comes from Plato’s Parmenides, an account of an encounter between Socrates, Parmenides, and Zeno which occurred before Plato was born, and which is undoubtedly biased. For example, Plato seems to associate Parmenides’ description of “the One” with his own subtle conception of Platonic forms. In my mind, this cannot be reconciled with Zeno’s paradoxes, which every ancient commentator (including Plato) agrees were constructed to support Parmenides. The paradoxes, in my view, place geometry and mathematics squarely into the world of “the many” (appearances), and thus represent Zeno’s attempt to prove that observations and measurements of the world we see and experience around us cannot provide “true” knowledge of reality (i.e., reality is mismatched with our thoughts and conceptions). With this (admittedly questionable) interpretation of Zeno, I draw a line from him to early Greek skepticism and in particular to the academic skepticism of Carneades and Clitomachus a couple of centuries later. As I hope to show in future posts, modern biology (in light of evolutionary theory) forces us to skepticism about our ability to know the physical world “as it is,” yet this biology-driven skepticism is no barrier to modern science. Indeed, it explains why the sciences are necessarily empirical and why the scientific method is successful (and why other methods are not). It is a viewpoint, as far as I can determine, surprisingly similar to that of Carneades and Clitomachus (if only we had their writings, which we don’t).

 

Posted in Uncategorized | Leave a comment

Georges Lemaître & Naturalism as History

Throughout the history of science, the naturalistic turn of mind has been to look for a history for physical stuff. And the supernaturalistic turn of mind has been the opposite. Plato famously excluded a history for the world by postulating eternal forms, and in Western thought afterwards only human society was seen as having a history: outside mankind, the physical world was essentially unchanged over time. If it had any history at all, it consisted in one-time creation by eternal God or divine Mind. 

During the early modern period, the discovery of fossils created doubts about this unchanging nature of the world. Although many scientists initially pushed back and denied that fossils were relics of previous forms of animals, eventually the evidence became undeniable. Those scientists with a naturalistic turn began to look for explanations of how species might evolve and change over time—that is, to develop a natural history. 

As we know, this eventually led to Charles Darwin’s identification of natural selection as the key ingredient of speces’ evolution (just as artificial selection was the key to evolution of domesticated animals).

In the 20th century, Georges Lemaître proposed what is today called the “Big Bang” origin of the universe, in opposition to the bent of Fred Hoyle’s Steady State theory. Where Hoyle limited the history of the universe to development of stars from an original hydrogen cloud, Lemaître pushed that history back to an earlier non-uniform quantum/plasma state. 

In a recently rediscovered 1964 interview, he explained his opposition to creation stories (whether pantheistic or theistic) and in fact he saw his own theory as one that precluded a creation story for the universe. See https://arxiv.org/pdf/2301.07198.pdf for a transcript of this interview. [GLM = Georges Lemaître]

GLM: [A] very long time ago, before the theory of the expansion of the universe (some 40 years ago), we expected the universe to be static. We expected that nothing would change. It was an a priori idea that applied to the whole universe… [interrupted by JV]

JV: …that was consistent with experiment… [interrupted by GLM]

GLM: No, not at all. Not at all! It was an a priori idea. For which there was no experiment. And the facts relating to the expansion of the universe made this theory inadmissible. So we realized that we had to admit change. But those who wanted for there to be no change wanted to minimize this change. In a way, they would say: ”while we can only admit that it changes, it should change as little as possible”. Let it change only in scale. That everything happens on a larger scale but that it happens in the same way. And this is what was first introduced by Milne [Edward Arthur Milne, Fellow of the Royal Society] under the name of ”cosmological principle” and later under the name of ”perfect cosmological principle” and then by the very idea of the Steady State Theory.

He goes on to criticize the Steady State Theory as an attempt to buttress a supernatural worldview.

So this is how this theory presents itself. As a theory imposing an assumption analogous to the apriori that you should look for a static solution … [unclear] … that you are looking for a solution with a minimum of change. Which, for my part, along with others, I am opposed to [that static solution] in the sense that I don’t think that it is the tendency of modern physics to admit that there are global laws in the universe, absolute laws, laws that, in Hoyle’s expression, would imply a ”design”, would imply a plan. I cannot picture things working that way.

Thus Lemaître is not just insisting on a history for everything physical, his naturalistic mindset also pushes back against the notion of universal a priori laws of physics.

So that from the point of view of astronomical development of the whole universe, we find ourselves with distinct gaseous clouds which are almost entirely made up of hydrogen. Now this is the key point of Hoyle’s theory: it all starts with hydrogen. The essential difference is whether this hydrogen is produced naturally by a reasonable physical process or, on the contrary, it is a kind of phantom hydrogen which appears with just the right amount of hydrogen to verify an a priori law.

In the 20th century, Lemaître’s discovery of the expansion of the universe (from the red-shift of starlight) led to the scientific realization that the universe had a history. The steady-state theory was a response that wrote that history back to primordial hydrogen and stopped there. But Lemaître argued that cosmic rays (similar to the discovery of fossils in rocks) meant that the history of the universe went back even further. (The discovery of the cosmic microwave background radiation shortly before his death added an exclamation point!)

This is a theory that was put forward not only by myself, but by Regener [Erich Rudolf Alexander Regener] a long time ago, who called cosmic rays fossil rays in the sense that they are the testimony of the very first ages of the world. And I, for my part, preferred to call them the rays of the primeval fireworks, which are preserved in the remarkably empty space and reach us… giving us a testimony of the first ages of the world… obviously, a bit of poetry in there.

At this point the interviewer asked him,

[D]oes the fact that the universe, according to your theory, has a beginning (at least one beginning)… does it have a religious meaning for you, a religious significance?

Lemaître was reluctant to discuss religion (even though he was a Catholic priest as well as astronomer and theoretical physicist), but he was willing to talk about the notion of the universe being created.

When one poses the problem of the beginning of the world, one is almost always faced with a rather essential difficulty: to ask oneself, why did it begin at that moment? Why didn’t it start a little earlier? And in a certain sense, why wouldn’t it have started a little earlier? So it seems that any theory that involves a beginning must be unnatural. [emphasis added]  To say ”we decide at this point that it begins”… This is what was expressed by saying: ”it is made of nothing”. That is to say that we expected it to come from something; and we say ”it doesn’t come from this something, it’s made of nothing”. Well… the point of view I’m coming to is quite different. That is, the beginning is so unimaginable, so different from the present state of the world that such a question does not arise. And even more than that. This beginning is the beginning of multiplicity. The fundamental idea is… I can’t develop it with more details now… it is the beginning of multiplicity. It is the idea that the universe, which exists in quanta, in packets of determined energy, begins with a single quantum, or a very small number of quanta, so that it is impossible to wonder from what it would come, from what it would have been divided from. The whole development of entropy is that quanta divide themselves, develop, etc. At the beginning, if there is only one, we cannot ask ourselves where it comes from. Then the question does not arise to say that it comes from nothing. It is a background of space-time for which no problem arises. Or if you want, when one holds oneself as the spiritualist, with the idea that it comes from God, etc. … well, one would like to take God in default for this ’initial flick’ as Laplace [Pierre-Simon, Marquis de Laplace] said. Well it doesn’t hold, because the beginning… the bottom of the space-time is so different from all our conceptions that there is no more problem. And then obviously for an atheist, everything/anything cannot remain, I cannot continue to speak if God doesn’t support me in the existence, that’s for sure, isn’t it? But that’s nothing, that’s the general stance of christian philosophy. But there’s nothing special about the beginning. And the beginning is not a place where you would touch God as a hypothesis, where if you like, I’ll talk about Laplace’s initial flick, since we’re now talking about conferences in English… I recall Jeans [Sir James Hopwood Jeans, Fellow of the Royal Society] words ”the finger of God agitating the ether” [dramatic voice], that was the beginning. Well, that’s not… that’s not a pleasant idea for a religious mind. It’s an idea that brings God down into the realm of primary causes, and I think one of the contributions that a theory like mine can make is to avoid just such difficulties.

JV: So, to state things plainly, you refuse to accept the idea that God should explain the movement of galaxies.

GLM: Of course, it goes without saying! Absolutely.

Although Lemaître was a Catholic priest (the epitome of someone with a supernatural worldview, it would seem), when it came to studying the physical world his mindset was, as we have seen, very naturalistic. He devoutly separated his scientific mindset from his religious mindset, nor did he see a conflict in doing so. The Wikipedia article on him states,

In relation to Catholic teaching on the origin of the Universe, Lemaître viewed his theory as neutral with neither a connection nor a contradiction of the Faith; as a devoted Catholic priest, Lemaître was opposed to mixing science with religion,[16] although he held that the two fields were not in conflict.[37]  https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Georges_Lemaître (captured Feb 4, 2023) Wikipedia’s sources for this interpretation are Lambert, Dominique (1997). “Monseigneur Georges Lemaître et le débat entre la cosmologie et la foi (à suivre)”. Revue Théologique de Louvain (in French). 28 (1): 28–53. doi:10.3406/thlou.1997.2867. ISSN 0080-2654 and https://www.bbc.co.uk/blogs/ni/2012/06/father_of_the_big_bang.html 

Ironically, Lemaître’s adversary in the field of astronomy, Fred Hoyle (despite being a self-described atheist), lacked this naturalistic mindset. Hoyle believed there was intelligent design behind the origin of life.

Rather than accept the fantastically small probability of life having arisen through the blind forces of nature, it seemed better to suppose that the origin of life was a deliberate intellectual act. …

A common sense interpretation of the facts suggests that a superintellect has monkeyed with physics, as well as with chemistry and biology, and that there are no blind forces worth speaking about in nature. —Fred Hoyle, “The Universe: Past and Present Reflections”, Engineering and Science, November 1981, p. 12. https://calteches.library.caltech.edu/527/2/Hoyle.pdf

In contrast, those with a naturalistic turn of mind understand implicitly that mind-stuff (including intellect) is not primary. They comprehend the mistake of inserting consciousness, intelligence, or conceptual laws in order to jump-start the history of the universe. In this vein, we must admire Lemaître’s opposition to a priori laws of physics, and appreciate his reluctance to insert God (consciousness or mind) as creator of some beginning state of the universe—much less as manager of its development. Lemaître rejected the lazy human tendency to forego investigation of the past in favor of simplified, automatic answers.

Instead: history—without origin in formula or theology. 

And this “history” is just homo sapiens, as scientists, figuring out best we can what has happened. 

Human thought naturally wants to start at a beginning and stop at an end. But this instinct of human thought is biological; it is not a priori, it doesn’t apply to the physical universe.

__

*Georges Lemaître Interview link: https://arxiv.org/pdf/2301.07198.pdf

Posted in Atheology, Evolution & ID, Naturalism, Supernaturalism | Comments Off on Georges Lemaître & Naturalism as History

Mastodon

You can now follow me on Mastodon.

Posted in Uncategorized | Comments Off on Mastodon

Muse is the Antidote

My poetic muse has always been an alter-ego, chastising me for being too much in my head, too cerebral. Looking back over the years I can see that my muse has presented a more or less consistent message: life is not at heart about my thoughts and feelings. Life is not a mental enterprise.

It was when I was a college student that the muse first rebelled against my studious nature.

It was an all-out rebellion.

Not with profanity nor profundity (anathema to my muse) nor with any pretension of depth, but with simple derision toward intellectual conceits. Nor at first did I understand what was going on with her. I would grab books and sit by a pond to study or write a paper. And out of my unexpecting pen would come this…

Battle of the Books

So he went down after classes
and sat there by the lake
and pulled out his books to study for a test…

Well the lake rose up in splashes
saying, “Go back to your classes
And read your books until your brain is pleased,
Sittin’ in your molded chair
Thinkin’ you’re so cool you stare
To find some beauty in the books you read.”

Oh the lake rose up in splashes
And thunder struck in lashes
Saying, “Go back to your classes
Or put those books away
Yeah, put those books away”

Oh the flowers screamed in horror
And the trees bent down in anger,
“Oh, put those books away,
Yeah, put those books away”

You can build your concrete cities
In all your valleys and your plains
And you can live inside your houses
And say that I’m insane
But please, don’t forget to play out in the rain

Her target was always me. And the message always consistent: the mind is not the central show of life. The role of the mind is not self-entertainment, self-advancement, enlightenment, intellectual fulfillment, profundity or any other self-deception.

No, muse insisted, the mind exists for the benefit of the body, not the other way round. And more than that: if I identify myself as mind, make my thoughts my identity, then I have become ill.

This impacts the the kind of poetry I end up creating.

The muse has sensibilities which disdain poetry of the head and reject intellectualized poetic expression. Which seems a bit strange—after all writing is an act of language, and forming words is a pre-eminently intellectual affair. Yet muse insists that I use language to escape the bounds of mentality, to speak out for my body somehow.

According to muse, I am a body and my mind belongs to that body—and must serve it. Not with lies, but with honesty.

And the central act of honesty is accepting that I am not my mind. My mind doesn’t even matter all that much. And if I slip into thinking that thinking is what life is all about, then I’m coming down with something, becoming ill, pushing myself into mental illness territory.

Time to get out of my head and get healthy again.

This has also served as a guide to my philosophical inquiry. Slowly, slowly, it has helped me understand what has been wrong with philosophy over the ages, and helped me surmise what lies in the right direction.

The first thing wrong with philosophy, by the way, is the word itself. Knowledge is not something that should be loved. It should be used: knowledge is a tool, not a destination.

To be a lover of thought, a lover of knowledge is already to start to slip into illness, because love of that sort carries the beguiling suggestion that life is about mind-stuff. That we are mind-stuff. That our “I am” lies in the realm of thoughts. This makes us diseased.

It also makes us liable to mental checkmate. Thoughts can become a quagmire of confusion and mis-direction which tie us into knots with no apparent way out. The result can be depression, even suicidal notions that we can escape by killing ourselves. But the problems are mental. The only thing we need escape from is our thoughts, our minds, our false belief that what we think, what others think, is the central show of life.

It’s not.

On the other hand, this should not be interpreted as a diatribe against thinking. Thoughts have a vital role to play in our living and surviving in the world. We can’t make it as a species without science, without understanding ourselves and our world. Still, our thoughts are not us. They are tools meant for our benefit.

Life is a bodily enterprise, not a mental one. If your thoughts, your feelings become checkmated, time to throw off those thoughts and feelings. They were never central to your life anyway, no matter how much it felt that way. Things in your head got unbalanced, mentally diseased. You fell into to the trap of thinking your thoughts were you, and now you must listen to your muse and escape back to bodily life, best you can.

This is the role of the creative or poetic muse, to lead us out of the valley of mental disease and back to the body. The muse is the lifeline to what we really are, which again is something beyond thought. Larger than thought, grander than thoughts could ever be.

And this is why it’s so important that we listen to the muse, honor her, make sure she is never compromised or co-opted into serving the mind. If anything, the mind should serve the muse. After all, she’s our lifeline out of mental checkmate.

Muse is the antidote to the disease of believing that we are minds, the only rope we have for climbing out of that deep, deep hole.


This article has also been published on Medium. Readers interested in my poetry can find it here

Posted in Atheist Culture, Meaning & Value, Uncategorized | Comments Off on Muse is the Antidote